Thursday, February 28, 2019
Aristotle and John Stuart Mill on Happiness and Morality
Aristotle and John Stuart powder on Happiness and Morality In this piece of music I onlyow argue that Aristotles conception of eudaemonia disproves wonks functional view that joyfulness is the gr expelest entire. The point of this study is to contrast Aristotles and molars views on the value of diversion and its attach to chasteneousness. First I will describe Aristotles model of well- beingness. thence I will present Mills utilitarian views on merriment and moralistics. Lastly, I will provide a counter wrinkle to Mills utilitarian honorable principles using the Aristotelian model of eudaimonia.In this section I will explain Aristotles definition of eudaimonia and its relationship to felicity, morality and the virtues. Aristotle defines eudaimonia in the first book of the Nicomachean Ethics as virgin scrapivity in accordance with reason and that this is the highest good for mankind beings. For Aristotle, eudaimonia mickle be translated into a human lifetim e of flourishing since it occurs throughout a souls life. This lifelong happiness is complete and enough in itself, sloppeding that a somebody lives it as an end in itself and non for anything else beyond it.An important aspect of reaching our own eudaimonia is to exercise well as human beings. Aristotle presents his concept of the human function by stating that what makes human function so distinct is non merely to obtain nutrition and to grow because that aspect of life is shargond with plants and it is besides non perception because that is something shared with animals. Our ultimate human function thusly is reason and not however if reason al iodine nevertheless to bit in accordance to reason. Achieving excellence in human rational use according to Aristotle is synonymous with adopting a moral life.To lead a moral life is a state in which a person chooses to act in accordance to the right virtues. Aristotle, defines virtue asa entail between two extremes (excess and deficiency). He argues that the mean is not unavoidably the average or half way point, but rather changes in relation to each individual. For example, a person who right finished continue needs more peeing after jogging than a person who was not jogging, so the mean between too much water and too little water is different for the jogger and non-jogger.According to Aristotle, it is very difficult to get out the mean, to discover the exact point between the two extremes that is best accommodate for you. As he says, there are many ways to be amiss(p) and only one way to be correct. Aristotle explains that the choice of the mean is going to depend on what the virtuous persons ratiocination is. As in the case of the jogger, he will drink just enough water to quench his thirst (deficiency) but wont drink too much that would result in water in water intoxication (excess).Aristotle focuses his moral theory on virtuous motion and argues that virtue is necessary, but not suffici ent for happiness. You need virtue to lead a happy life, but ultimately, virtue alone will not make you happy. What matters most is that you make a habit out of choosing to act in accordance with the right virtues, which leads to a balance in ones life and ultimately leads you closer and closer to achieving your own eudaimonia. In this next section I will present Mills utilitarian views and the link between happiness and morality and how his views do not concur with Aristotles eudaimonistic ideals.In chapter two of Utilitarianism, John Stuart Mill introduces his concept of utility, in like manner cognize as the Greatest Happiness Principle to hold that bodily functions are right in proportion as they tend to promote happiness, wrong as they tend to produce the reverse of happiness. By happiness is intended enjoyment, and the absence seizure of pain by unhappiness, pain, and the privation of pleasure. In other words, Mill makes it accredited that pleasure and freedom from pain a re the only things desirable as endings and all things that we do is desirable because they produce pleasure or proceed pain.Mill understood that it would be demeaning to humans to reduce life to pleasures as this would then put us at the same level as animals. Thus, he introduces the idea of higher(prenominal) and disgrace pleasures. The higher pleasures are those of a higher fictitious typeface of that are determined by commensurate judges. This competent judge is someone who is acquainted with two the higher and lower quality pleasures. In regards to morality, Mill anchors its definition on the premises of the greatest happiness principle stated above.Unlike Aristotle who puts emphasis on the agent (the person themselves) in regards to acting morally, Mill is very indifferent and states that the character of the person and their motives do not matter only the consequence of those actions matter. For Mill, the morality of the action only depends on whether that action wi ll produce pleasure for greatest bit of people. As state before, he explains that pleasure leads to happiness, and happiness is the ultimate goal of each individual. However, morality is the rules and precepts for human conduct, nd not simply the causes of human behavior. Desire may drive human actions, but that doesnt mean that desire should propel human actions. Morality is the ideal, not the reality. Because of his views on morality Mill would not agree with Aristotle that the completely ethical person will not be conflicted about his ethical choice. According to Mill a person could do the right thing, and act morally while also having the desire to do the wrong thing. To explain this, he gives the example of a rescuer who saves another person from drowning.He helps this person because it is morally right, regardless of being seen as a good Samaritan or if he wouldve been compensated for his actions. Mill would also disagree with Aristotles argument that it is determined whether or not someone led a eudaimonistic life only after this person has died. Mill essentially believes in concrete happiness and believes that people should be happy while they are alive. Mill states that pleasures are personas of our happiness and not an abstract means as Aristotle puts it.In this third section I will provide a counterargument to Mills utilitarian ethical principles using the Aristotelian model of eudaimonia. I firstly disagree with Mills idea that happiness is stand ford with pursuing acts that only lead to pleasure and avoiding those that decrease pleasure. I side completely with Aristotle in that he believes that the purpose of pleasures is to serve as side product of activity to perfect our activities. For example, for a mathematician to become an excellent mathematician he must become very knowing in doing mathematical activities but also must commence the pleasure in doing this activity.I also side with him on his statement in handwriting Ten of the Nicomac hean Ethics certain pleasures such as those of touch can lead us to become servile and brutish and says that it attaches to us not in so far as we are men but in so far as we are animals. For example those who eat food to the excess lose slavish characters because they are choosing to eat yesteryear their bodily intake limit. I agree here with Aristotle that those persons who are devoid of self-control do not use their reason, take pleasures exceedingly, in the wrong way and in the wrong objects.Ultimately, in order to act chastely a person must act rationally in a manner that is between the two extremes of deficiency and excess when it comes to matters of pleasure. Thus, pleasure should not be sought just for its own sake. In terms of moral actions, Mill arguments also seem to be flawed. He believes that the goodness of an action is based on whether or not it produced pleasure and happiness for the greatest number of people. There is little emphasis on the disposition and char acter of the agent performing the action.This idea seems illogical because then everyone would be acting without reason and doing things for the wrong intentions. As Aristotle says in Book One of the Nicomachean ethics, the man who does not rejoice in noble actions is not good the good man judges well in matters of the good and the noble. Here he is referring to the fact that a person who is not performing actions for the right intentions is not a good man at all. To explain this further I will use the example of the drowning person.Aristotle would advise that I should save a drowning person because I have the positive and noble intention to do so and not because someone is going to pay me for helping them. I think Mills view on happiness and morality that pleasures should equate with happiness sounds like it would be ideal to live this type of life. However, this type of logic would not work out in todays society. He tells us that in order to find out what kinds of pleasures are m ost valuable we should look to competent judges who seem to just know what are considered the better higher pleasures because they have experienced both the higher and lower pleasures.As Aristotle states, however, not all pleasures are universal to all men because not everyone is directed to the same things. What if their idea of a higher pleasure is to rape women on the streets? The problem with Mills argument then is that what this competent judge may consider to be a higher pleasure may actually be a lower pleasure and be very wrong about what they consider to be right. Aristotle would respond to Mills statement that happiness should be concrete by stating that happiness in Mills view seems to just be a fleeting experience.For example, if a person spends their whole life hard to figure out a cure for cancer it wont be determined whether this persons life work was meaning(prenominal) only until we examine this persons life work. To conclude, I have stated both Aristotles and Mil ls arguments in relation to happiness and morality. Aristotles conclude that happiness (eudaimonia) is to have flourishing life in which actions are performed in accordance to virtuousness and reason.Mill, on the hand believes that pleasure is ultimately the greatest type of good and therefore is equated with happiness. I have argued that Aristotles concept of eudaimonia disproves Mills greatest happiness priniciple on the grounds that pleasure is only a small part of happiness and that the emphasis on living a happy life should be placed on the agent to habitually act in a rational and virtuous manner.
Subscribe to:
Post Comments (Atom)
No comments:
Post a Comment